(Public Lecture, Philosophy Day, Notre Dame University, Cotabato City, 2010)
Classical utilitarianism argues that the basic moral value is utility or welfare. The basic moral good in this sense is that which is most beneficial. As such, the moral act is one that is aimed at the achievement of material satisfaction or gain. The human person, in this regard, is only secondary. The right act is always the achievement of the optimum benefit. This undermines the moral worth of the person, for ultimately, the person can be used in order to achieve maximum utility.
Classical utilitarianism argues that the basic moral value is utility or welfare. The basic moral good in this sense is that which is most beneficial. As such, the moral act is one that is aimed at the achievement of material satisfaction or gain. The human person, in this regard, is only secondary. The right act is always the achievement of the optimum benefit. This undermines the moral worth of the person, for ultimately, the person can be used in order to achieve maximum utility.
Justice as Fairness
John Rawls’ A Theory of Justice, published at a time when political theory was made dormant by the excursions of most philosophers in the field of language analysis, is a response to utilitarianism. In this work,
he attempts to reconcile freedom and equality. The idea, precisely, is to value
each person as equals while at the same time, respecting their autonomy.
The establishment of the basic structure, for Rawls, fulfills this moral ideal. According
to Rawls, “justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems
of thought.”[1]
Rawls, who
belongs to the social contract tradition of Kant and Rousseau, develops his
theory of justice from what he calls the original position, a device in which “all
parties choose the principles of justice from behind a veil of ignorance”. The
veil of ignorance deems that people who participate in the design of the
political apparatus do not know their status in society. They are essentially
blind to all the facts about their lives that might affect what notion of
justice they would agree. Rawls explains:
No one knows his place in society,
his class position or social status, nor does anyone know his fortune in the
distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence, strength, and
the like. I shall even assume that the parties do not know their conceptions of
the good or their special psychological propensities. The principles of justice
are chosen behind a veil of ignorance.[2]
The veil of
ignorance ensures that no one is in a position to take advantage of others in
choosing the principles of justice. Rawls points out that “they are the
principles that rational and free persons concerned to further their own
interests would accept in an initial position of equality as [rightly] defining the
fundamentals of the terms of their association”.[3]
Politics, from the point of view of utilitarianism, is sometimes about
sacrificing the weak, the disadvantaged, and the vulnerable for the greater
good or benefit of the majority. Proponents of utilitarianism used as context
the feudal history of Old England, where the elite minority simply took advantage
of the poor who constituted the majority of the English population then. It is
for this reason that utilitarianism speaks of the “greater good of the
majority”.
In terms of its epistemic status,
Rawls says that the original position is hypothetical in nature. Rawls argues
that these principles are in fact what the parties would agree upon if they
were in that hypothetical situation of the original position. Rawls explains this
by calling upon us “to imagine a state of nature where we are blind as to our
status or position in society”.[4]
This includes, for all members of society, not knowing where one would end up
or which fortunes one gets in the natural lottery. Under this veil of
ignorance, the position of equality is guaranteed. It ensures that those who
might be able to influence the process in their favor, due to their better
position in society, are unable to do so.[5] This
means, more importantly, that justice is about “protecting the weak and
innocent” against the abuses of the strong and “binding the powerful” to the
full moral force of the law.
The veil of ignorance indicates that
individuals must be responsible for their judgments but not for the situations
or circumstances beyond them, for instance, nationality, gender, or race. It is
for this reason that equality means “equal opportunity for all”. There must be
just distribution of social primary goods for equal opportunity requires that
basic structure compensates for the unequal circumstances men and women are
born into. Rawls says that:
Human beings should have the same
initial expectations of "basic goods," i.e., all-purpose goods; this
in no way precludes ending up with different quantities of such goods or
resources, as a result of personal economic decisions and actions. When prime
importance is accorded an assurance of equal basic freedoms and rights,
inequalities are just when they fulfill two provisos: on the one hand, they
have to be linked to offices and positions open to everyone under conditions of
fair equality of opportunity; on the other hand, they have to reflect the
famous ‘difference principle’ in offering the greatest possible advantage to
the least advantaged members of society.[6]
Herein, the initial status quo
is meant to emphasize the moral equality of human beings. This moral equality suggests
that it is not only the case that each person is free, but that there is
equality in terms of the freedom of each person. Ideally, it requires a
condition wherein no one can assert a privileged position in society, for the
rights of each must be something that one deserves on the basis of his or her
person. According to Will Kymlicka, the idea of “equal opportunity” means that
people “must not be disadvantaged by race or class”. Their condition must be
determined “as a matter of choice”, and they must not suffer on the basis of
certain circumstances that come as a result of the natural lottery of life. The
kind of life one lives, hence, is something that one must deserve. Ergo, the
poor do not deserve to suffer from their undeserved situation or circumstance, just as the
rich should not benefit from unfair or unjust systems.
In relation to the above, justice as
fairness makes it a moral imperative that the moral value of individual freedom
far outweighs the general welfare for if one person is to be sacrificed for the
good of all then that would be a violation of the basic principle of justice as
fairness. This is because, according to Rawls, each person, from the point of
view of liberal justice, possesses an inviolable value that not even the
welfare of society can override.[7] In
classical utilitarianism, as we have said at the outset, the good consists in
maximizing overall welfare, even if that sacrifices the minority. For
utilitarianism, general welfare is prioritized over the basic liberty of each.
This basically violates the person’s basic autonomy – the person’s very essence
– for he or she is reduced to a mere means to an end in order for the majority
to achieve whatever they so desire.
The Principles of Justice
Rawls asserts that the assurance
of the moral equality of all parties means that people would adopt two
principles of justice as theorized by in the liberal position in the
hypothetical contract.
These two principles, the priority
of liberty and the difference principle, would then govern the social
arrangement, including how certain rights, duties, social and economic
opportunities are to be distributed. The two principles of justice: First: each
person is to have an equal right to the most extensive scheme of equal basic
liberties compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for others. Second,
that social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that, a) offices
and positions must be open to everyone under conditions of fair equality of
opportunity and b) they are to be of the greatest benefit to the
least-advantaged members of society (the difference principle).[8]
The first
principle, or the autonomy principle, suggests that the liberty of the
individual is inviolable. The liberty principle is supreme and cannot be
violated for the sake of the second principle. This is because the autonomy or
liberty of the individual essentially constitutes his moral value. No person,
in this sense, can be sacrificed for the sake of another good nor can a person
be used as means to further another end. Meaning to say, personal liberty means
that the person is an end in itself. A liberal state guarantees the autonomy of
each person, but he or she must not undermine the liberty of others nor exploit
others to his or her advantage.
The second principle, the fair
opportunity principle and the difference principle, considers how social
primary goods like income, opportunity, and the basis of self-respect, can be
distributed from a just social arrangement. First, Rawls says that government
instrumentalities, i.e. offices, elections, must be open to all under the fair
terms of cooperation. This means that every person must have the chance to take
advantage of the benefits or advantages that the institutions of government can
make available. This includes, among others, the right to run for office.
Secondly, it is the worst off in society who must be favored primarily to make
the distribution of social primary goods just.
The basic point is that in this
condition of equal opportunity for all, people can pursue their life-plans and
profit from the same, but they must contribute through taxes to serve the worst
off[9] or
the disadvantaged, an adjustment meant to ensure that the worst off can have
the opportunity to improve their lives. This is what the famous difference
principle calls for. Fairness in the liberal sense therefore means that justice
is served when we treat people as equals, “not by removing all inequalities,
but only those which disadvantage the worst off”.[10]
Equality in the liberal sense
therefore means that each person’s liberty is construed as the moral basis of
society. Any person who may have an advantage in view of his talent can still
pursue his ambition of wealth creation as long as the inequality brought about
by his competence, talent or ability ultimately favors those who might enjoy
the benefits resulting from his actions.
By way of a
simple illustration, say if a person gains more income say from being a manager
of a bank, the inequality is not necessarily unjust if his access to more
income serves the interests of his clients, who in turn must also serve the
interest of their customers, most of which could belong to the lower end of the economic spectrum. Businessmen must sell goods at a fair price for its
opposite means exploitation. Or for example, if a person invests his shares
from social primary goods and earns some profit, there is no injustice if
people benefit from his investments, say from gainful employment. Entitlement
to the profit that one’s basic liberties allow, granting such profit is not
acquired nor used to the disadvantage of the worst off, forms as the firm
foundation of liberal equality.
According to Will Kymlicka, liberal
equality follows from what Rawls calls the maximin strategy. Say, for instance,
we have situations A, B, and C for three distinct people who are given the following
amount of primary social goods: A – 10,000:8,000:1,000; B – 7,000:6,000:2,000; C –
5,000:4,000:4,000. Since people do not know where they will end up in the just
distribution, one should maximize his or her chances of getting an adequate
amount of goods and minimize the risks of getting into the bottom. In this
case, it would be rational to choose C, for it maximizes your chances and your
risks are little if you end up getting the minimum. A is a form of oligarchy,
where there are two sectors or perhaps families in society enriching themselves
perpetually, and making use of the less well off. B does not fare better, for
there’s still a gap, and since nobody knows where one would end up, nobody
would agree to such a condition. C seems to show that there is some form of
inequality, but such can be compensated by the fact that the less well-off at
least possesses a chance to catch up, given the fact that the rich is not too
rich to usurp everybody, and that the poor is not too despondent that life is in
such a terrible state that it means nothing to the person.
Critique of Liberal Equality
Liberal equality is not a perfect theory.
For instance, following Ronald Dworkin, it can be argued that the difference
principle accounts only for disadvantages in terms of social primary goods and
neglects natural disadvantages like mental disabilities.[11]
Dworkin says that even if social primary goods are redistributed, those with
disabilities will still be disadvantaged because of their condition. Thus, for
Dworkin a certain form of insurance must first be provided to those with natural
disabilities before the resources of society are auctioned off. Justice as
fairness demands in this sense that it must be endowment sensitive. This will
ensure that the distribution of resource will not be biased to those with
natural disabilities.
It is also important to point out
that people, being free, can waste their fair share due to bad choices. But it
is also argued in the text that it is equally unjust for one to demand that
someone else pay for the overall cost of one’s choices simply because one has
misappropriated what has been allocated to him/her as his/her fair share. Thus,
the difference principle must be ambition-sensitive. Here, Kymlicka, following
Dworkin, makes the analogy of the tennis player and the gardener who are
provided with the same resource, the former opting for leisure while the latter
wisely investing the said resource through hard work.
We can improve on his analogy by
citing a real world example instead. Say Pupil A and Pupil B go to the same
public school – Pupil A drops out whereas Pupil B succeeds. Let’s find out why.
Ambition-sensitivity is an important account, but I am using a real world
example to be more reflective of reality. I would like to say that it is a fact
that there is a great imbalance in terms of access to society’s resource. Much
is invested in private education by way of grants, tuitions, endowments, but,
like in our case, so little is put into public education, creating a huge
disparity in terms of the kind of education received by rich and poor children.
Both Pupil A and Pupil B go to the same public school, but it is a fact that
Pupil A might fail although they are given the same resource in the same manner
as both the tennis player and gardener were given the same resource. Why? The
reason is that basic needs may not even be adequate in the first place! What
Dworkin emphasizes in the idea of ambition sensitivity is that individuals must
be responsible for the goods allocated for them.
Fairness is discussed generally in
terms of equality of opportunity, which suggests that a bigger income is
deserved as long as there has been fair competition.[12]
But such notion of fair competition can put those who do not possess high
intelligence or skill at a disadvantage. The concept of fair competition is
deceptive because others have natural talents they do not deserve to possess if
we put premium in the moral equality of persons. The central argument of Rawls
then is that all social arrangements, to be fair, should ultimately favor the
worst off, whose disadvantage, say in their social position or natural talent
is something they don’t deserve.
So how is liberal egalitarianism
attained in view of social inequality? Liberal theorists focus on the second
principle of justice – the difference principle. This principle provides for
the basis of a theory of just redistribution. Why redistribute the resources of
society? The argument for this is that I believe if the rich are left on their
own, chances are they will be using the worst off to advance their interests.
Justice as fairness ensures that enough opportunities are available to the
worst-off. How is this done? For Rawls, this means removing inequalities which
disadvantage people by giving them a just share of the social primary goods. As
an example, a landlord who gains 60 percent of the share of harvests is simply
taking advantage of a farmer who gains only 40 percent out of which he will
also have to pay for farm implements, fertilizers, etc. apart from the fact
that he is the one who tills the land. This form of inequality is unacceptable.
To remove this form of injustice, a democratic state can implement land reform.
However, it can be argued that the
distribution of resources in terms of income only touches the superficial
symptoms of poverty but does not address the differences and heterogeneities
between two people. For instance, person A and B can have the same amount of
income. But if person A is a person with a physical handicap, there is no real
equality though they have the same amount of income. The difference principle
is good, but not good enough.[13]
The income approach only addresses the poverty of income but not the poverty of
human life. Unjust social arrangements diminish the capabilities of people, and
as such, re-arranging the mode of social cooperation therefore entails looking
at holistic approaches to development. For instance, if we consider those with
natural disabilities, it is not income that they need but a sense of human
well-being beyond what economic provisions provide.
Rawls on Global Justice
Justice serves the purpose of the basic
structure set up under the rule of one sovereign government. This relation
within the basic structure is political, not moral. This political relation is
established by way of the legitimacy citizens confer upon their government. The
power of a sovereign state towards its members defines the basis and limits of
such associative relation. This associative relation can be defined as state
membership. It is only through such that citizens can claim, Thomas Nagel says, “a
right to democracy, equal citizenship, non-discrimination, equality of
opportunity, and the amelioration through public policy fairness in the
distribution of social and economic goods.” Rawls suggests "equality of peoples", which for Nagel, is a mere ideal considering the fact that equality is a domestic case - a matter of citizenship.
Thomas Pogge argues for a global difference principle. Pogge, for
instance, in Realizing Rawls, suggests
that liberal equality limits justice to the domestic case and disregards the
reality of global poverty. The basic structure in Rawls's view treats only the problem of
redistribution at the local level, whereas injustice due to unfair and unjust
global structures harm individuals in disadvantaged nations, specifically those
in the third world. Global injustice involves the problem of exclusion. People
from outside the community of a nation state are excluded from the rights,
privileges and opportunities that come with citizenship.
It is important
to consider, however, that in the global arena the wealth produced in a developed
economy is not necessarily and exclusively from its own natural resources, but
involves a complex and vast network or apparatus of global trade which entail
using resources from the third world, both material and human, for the benefit
of developed countries. Redistribution, hence, must go beyond the duty of
assistance. It should involve the transfer of resources and technology,
including ending unjust global structural barriers, in order to create a more
egalitarian world.
The
points above imply that global inequality, the imbalance of wealth between rich
and poor nations, and the economic suffering that it brings is not a problem
that the basic structure of rich nations must address. The political relation
of citizens does not give rise to the obligations of justice to outsiders. Pogge, argues that “by seeing the problem of poverty merely in terms of assistance, we
overlook that our economic advantage is deeply tainted by how it accumulated
over the course of one historical process that has devastated other societies.”
Joseph Stiglitz echoes the same when he revealed how the policies of the
International Monetary Fund have actually stymied development rather than
uplift the lives of the global poor.
While the citizens of rich countries
look down upon migrant workers, it must be noted that rich countries also
benefit from them. Nation building in countries like Singapore and Saudi Arabia
has been at the expense of the least advantaged citizens of poor nations who
labor doing the dirty jobs they offer. Unjust policies of certain states, for
instance in Singapore, which limit migrant workers access to government
institutions make them poor victims of maltreatment. State governments owe
these workers the justice they deserve. From a cosmopolitan end, global structures need to be adjusted to make the playing field fair. These adjustments do not require the diminution of state sovereignty. The greatest scandal to humanity is the fact that the economic growth of rich nations has always been at the expense of the poorest of the poor in the Third world.
References:
Dworkin, Ronald. Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977.
Kymlicka, Will. Contemporary Political Philosophy, (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2007).
Rawls, John. A Theory of Justice, (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1971).
_________. Political Liberalism, (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1993).
Sen, Amartya. Development as Freedom, (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1999).
Pogge, Thomas. Realizing Rawls (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press 1989).
[1] John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 3.
[2] Ibid.,
11.
[3] Ibid. By
“rational and free”, Rawls means persons who can give their consent and can
justify giving that consent.
[4] Ibid.
[5] Will Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy,
(Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2007), 63.
[6] John
Rawls, Political Liberalism, (New York: Columbia University Press,
1993), 5.
[7] See
Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 11-13
[8] Ibid.,
47
[9] The
worst off refers to those who are disadvantaged in society, for instance,
members of poor communities, those who belong to cultural minorities, or the
individuals in sectors which are vulnerable due to their social condition, i.e.
poverty, conflict, disabilities, etc.
[10] Kymlicka,
Contemporary Political Philosophy, 55.
[11] Ibid.,
59
[12] Ibid.,
57
[13] See Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom,
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).