Saturday, June 16, 2018

Book Chapter: Three Basic Moral Principles

(Excerpts, Applied Ethics: Moral Possibilities for a Contemporary World, 2008)

The Ethics of Virtue

Moral virtue, Socrates says, is rooted in moral wisdom. Moral wisdom refers to one’s knowledge of the good. What is the moral good? The opposite of wisdom is ignorance. Virtue is the knowledge of the good. A person of virtue therefore is a man of wisdom. Moral wisdom requires self-examination. Wisdom, Socrates tells us, is about “knowing thyself.”

The practice of the good is called phronesis. For Aristotle, moral virtue signifies the capacity to be excellent in doing things. Moral wisdom does not come from a single act of kindness or honesty. It is a habit. It is grounded in the way a person lives. As such, it comes from the practice of the good. This constitutes what moral character is all about.

Individuals act, according to the above notion of moral virtue, in pursuit of human happiness. The goal of every human action is happiness. This means that people must utilize things only as means. But this, more often than not, is misunderstood. Because of ignorance, people often equate happiness with material pleasure.

It can be recalled that Plato understood the good life as a life that is governed by a sense of harmony. Just like Aristotle, goodness and virtue are linked, for their unity produces harmony. For Plato, the good life is one that can be pictured out in terms of the efficient functioning of instruments. For instance, a knife is good if it cut wells. In the same manner, a human being is good if he develops a similar kind of efficiency.

The formation of human character results in the realization of a happy life. For Aristotle, happiness is the state of living well. Aristotle says: “Every virtue or excellence both brings into good condition the thing of which it is the excellence and makes the work of that thing be done well…therefore, if this is true in every case, the virtue of man also will be the state of character which makes a man good and makes him do his own work well.” (NE 2:6)    
 
Self-Perfection

Aristotle thinks that the human being possesses a distinctive function to fulfill. Aristotle explains his moral theory through the constitution of the human being. Aristotle says that the human being is composed of body and soul. For him, the soul is the seat of control while the body is the instrument. It is the soul that commands the body. The soul, Aristotle believes, consists of rational and irrational elements. The rational element is the intellect. It is the center that determines how human beings must act.

The irrational part of the human soul consists of the vegetative and the appetitive elements. The vegetative element deals with the body’s organic growth, seen as the lowest part of the soul. The other part is the appetitive element which deals with human emotions and desires. Human beings have feelings of fear and anxiety or the emotion of joy and resentment. What the individual does is sometimes based on these impulses. The basic idea is for the human being to be able to control these impulses, and direct the soul to the morally virtuous act.

It is the intellect that regulates human action, and for this reason, it is the highest element of the human soul. In relation to this, Aristotle explains the meaning of moral virtues. He says that “virtue, being of two kinds, the intellectual and moral: man’s intellectual virtue owes its birth and growth to teaching while moral virtue comes about as a result of habit.” (NE 2:1) Now, the key to its explanation comes from the [doctrine of the mean]. The human being must seek the middle when he acts. Aristotle tells us:

Virtue, then, is a state of character concerned with choice, lying in the mean, i.e. the mean relative to us, this being determined by a rational principle, and by that same principle by which the man of practical wisdom would determine it. (NE 2:6)

The self can achieve perfection through phronesis. Our moral virtues, according to Aristotle, are not mental capacities. Rather, these are character traits. Character refers to the human being’s ability to choose in such a way that his actions are neither excessive nor inadequate. Such requires a form of self-mastery. This self-mastery constitutes the meaning of good character.

Thus, a person who is courageous possesses the virtue of courage. This means that in the face of many risks, he knows and acts in a particular way exhibiting such a trait. Moral virtue, in this regard, helps the individual attain self-perfection, which is the realization of the potentials of the soul. Virtue defines a person’s character, which is the ultimate goal of the individual.

Aristotle says that ethics is concerned with what constitutes the finality of our action. Thus, Aristotle writes in Nichomachean Ethics: “All activities aim at some good. Every art and human inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, aim at some good; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim.” (NE 1:1)

Human Happiness

The objects of human desire or the things that people pursue are not in themselves the highest good. Material things are temporary whereas virtue is eternal. Things have a certain sense of limitation. It is only moral virtue that lasts. Aristotle thinks that “the life of money-making is one undertaken with compulsion, and wealth is evidently not really the good we are seeking; for it is merely useful and for the sake of something else.” (NE 1:5)

Goods like money, honor or power are desired not for their own sake, but for the sake of something else higher. Material wealth brings pleasure; honor begets pride; and political power brings influence. But all these goods cannot be the ultimate goal of human life. In searching for this finality, men must act morally to attain the good life.

Aristotle explains that “verbally there is general agreement; for the general run of men of superior refinement say that it is truly human happiness, and identify living well and doing well with being happy.” (NE 1:4) Happiness, it is said, defines the [good life]. It is a kind of life marked by excellence, a life that is fully worth living.

Aristotle says that people must seek the good. The good for Aristotle is concerned with the state of living well. The state living well is eudaimonia which for the Greeks means living the good life. It is more than the sense of satisfaction, which people often confuse with the real meaning of happiness. Happiness means that the good life consists of the life that is truly lived. It is that kind of life that flourishes with noteworthy human activity.
                                                                                   
Living well depends on the use of resources which serve as the means to attain the good. The ability to flourish enables each individual to achieve the highest end of human life. Happiness is never about the accumulation of material wealth. It goes beyond the ephemeral value of things. Only human happiness is desirable in itself. Other things are mere instruments for human happiness. Aristotle says:

Now, such a thing as happiness, above all else, is held to be; for this we choose always for itself, and never just for the sake of something else, but honor, pleasure, reason, and every virtue that we choose indeed for themselves, but we choose them also for the sake of happiness, judging that by means of them we shall be happy. Happiness, on the other hand, no one chooses for the sake of these, nor in general, for anything other than itself. (NE 2:7)

Well-being is expressed in dynamic activity. Living well, in this sense, is connected with doing or being able to act out what is necessary to realize the [good life]. Aristotle writes, “happiness seems… to come as a result of virtue and some process of learning and training.” (NE 2:9) An analogy can be made between flourishing and the gardener. The good gardener possesses all the skills and tools to be able to flourish in what he does. He cares for his plants and he also seriously loves his work. This habit makes itself manifest in his character.

It can be said that the gardener who gives his time and skill to improve his work is one who is truly able to find the fulfillment in what he is doing. Doing well means that one has the ability or real freedom to attain the good. In a way, living well means that the human person has all the opportunity to make proper choices in life that enables his unfolding. This unfolding refers to one’s self-realization. To realize oneself means that one is able to do the things that one finds valuable because these are things that contribute to the development of the human person.

The Ethics of Moral Obligation

Every person, Kant says, knows the meaning of the moral good. This knowledge is the source of moral duty. Moral duty, Kant thinks, is universal. It applies to all persons everywhere at all times. It is the fundamental law of our nature. Kant tells us that “the dignity of humanity consists in the ability of being universally legislating though with the very condition that it is also subject to the same legislation.”  (CI: 38)

Since the human being is capable of deliberating, following rules, and making free choices, he is subject to the moral law. (Holmes 2007:103) The rational nature of man presupposes his freedom. This means that man has the obligation to obey his rational nature. For Kant, the human will is good, not because the consequences are good, nor because it is capable of attaining the end which it seeks, “but it is good in itself, or because it wills the good.” (CI: 359)

The human person knows the good internally through the autonomy of the will. For Kant, duty is the supreme norm of morality or “the obligation to act from reverence to law.” (361) Kant then puts forward what is known as an a priori (meaning ‘prior to experience’) or a formal moral philosophy. He says that our moral principles are known a priori. Moral philosophy, in this regard, is pure and formal. Kant says that “the conception of duty, however, we must not derive from experience…the idea of duty as duty belongs to the idea of reason which determines the will on a priori grounds.” (262)

According to Kant, “nothing can possibly be conceived in the world or even out of it, which can be called good without qualification except a good will.” (Kant 2002: 33) All moral worth is determined by a [good will]. Kant, in this regard, “insists to derive any moral worth from our actions we must do them from the right motive.” (Holmes 2007: 101)

Morality for Kant proceeds from a moral ought. The moral ought, for Kant, is the fundamental moral principle governing the goodness of an action. All good emanates from the moral ought, which for Kant is not a description of the good, but an authoritative and normative principle. This principle dictates or commands our action. For Kant, the good is grounded in our moral obligation. (CI: 363)

Autonomy of the Will

Kant says that we are autonomous beings. Human action in this regard must be free from the influence of external factors. It can be said that outside reasons can influence the way people act. The social environment may affect our behavior. For Kant, a moral judgment should be free from the dictates of an external influence. Autonomy means [self-rule]. He writes,

Autonomy is the basis of the dignity of every human being and of every rational nature…although a conception of duty implies subjection to the moral law, people yet ascribe a certain dignity and sublimity to the person who fulfills his duty. (Kant 2002: 38)

The individual performs the [moral ought] in accordance to the inner law of the will. For Kant, autonomy is the property of the will. The [will] is the law by itself. The will legislates for itself. Thus, the autonomy of the will provides the moral agent the capacity to legislate the moral law within. Since the law comes from within, a person is required to do the good accordingly. Otherwise, the individual violates his capacity for self-rule. 

The idea of moral duty proceeds from the notion of moral agency. For Kant, the moral agent is one who acts on the basis of a rational will. A good act by any moral agent is determined through his rational capacity. The basic idea is that a good act is that which an agent does by following the moral law within. Kant views the [good will] as good in itself. A good will is not dependent on outside objects or circumstances. Kant writes:

By a good will is not meant mere well-wishing; it consists in a resolute employment of the means within one’s reach and its intrinsic value is no way increased by success or lessened by failure. (CI: 359)

Thus, we pursue the good life or anything good in this world, say a career or a decent way of life, not because we desire certain values these give to us, but because we have a duty to fulfill the moral law within. An act is moral on the basis that it is the right thing to do. This righteousness proceeds from a good will alone. What matters in this regard is the intention, that is, the pure intention of doing what is good.

The external incentives of any reward or one’s skill in doing things do not qualify for the strict requirements Kant set for a good will. The ultimate motivation of the individual in his act must only be the will to do the good act itself. Meaning to say, a good act is performed because as rational beings we know that we are duty-bound to do so. In this sense, Kant would require that human individuals do not perform good acts because they are primarily motivated by profit or benefit.

A hypothetical imperative seeks to realize an outside inclination. Kant says that, “a hypothetical imperative states that a certain thing must be done, if something else which is willed is to be attained.” (363) The concept of a hypothetical imperative means that an action is good relatively to a certain possible end or to a certain end. (363) A hypothetical imperative implies that an act is done because of an external consequence, for instance, a reward.

For Kant, however, moral worth proceeds from a good will, not from an outside motive. The sole intention of the actor must be doing the act for its own sake. The good act has no other purpose except the fulfillment of a duty, which is the internal moral law of the human being. A perfectly [good will] would stand under our objective laws. (363) Thus, the ultimate good is simply doing what is good for its own sake. Kant says:

Good and pleasure are quite distinct. Pleasure results from the influence of subjective causes on the will of the subject, and these vary with the susceptibility of this or that person. (363)  

We can, for instance, compare motivation by duty with other sorts of motives. When the individual does something for the sake of his happiness or for the sake of being recognized, such things do not express a good will. The reason is that the individual seems to do things only to be praised, and this does not correspond to a good motive. A self-serving intent can destroy the morality of any act.

The “good will” does not desire self-promotion. Kant says that, “if the action is good in itself, the moral imperative, as a necessary principle of a will that conforms to reason, is categorical.” (363) It is the desire to do good that determines the moral value of an act and not the interest to benefit from doing something. Moral duty, in this regard, is a non-negotiable principle.

For Kant, the moral act is in itself necessary. It is without reference to another end. Henceforth, the categorical imperative is the single moral principle having the real spirit and dignity of being a moral law since it is the sole command that is absolute. For Kant, this authoritative dictate is a permanent imprint in the human subject whose nature is rational and free, through which we determine the absolute or categorical sense of morality

The Categorical Imperative

The categorical imperative promulgates what alone is to become the absolute moral obligation. Moral subjects are all duty-bound, otherwise, they would violate their own nature. In making a choice, man must follow what reason mandates. This implies that moral responsibility is inescapable for all rational beings. Such presupposes an absolute ought that alone defines what is right. The two salient principles of Kantian morality are as follows:

a.       Act as if the rule from which you act were to become through your will a universal law of nature. (365)

b.      Act so as to use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of another, always as an end, never merely as a means. (365)

First, universality means that a moral act is [unconditional] in nature. It is an absolute. This means that a moral act knows no boundaries. The right thing to do is always the right thing to do, whatever the circumstance, in all places at all times. Universality means that put in the same condition any individual would act in the same manner as another following the dictates of one’s duty.

For example, Kant asks if the act of breaking a promise can be morally justifiable. The answer, according to Kant, is a resounding ‘no’. The reason being is that doing so would destroy the essence of any promise, which is by the operation of one’s reason, is meant to be fulfilled. To fail a promise is to violate the very condition why a person makes a promise. If any man intends to be dishonest, then why make a commitment in the first place?

Second, the idea that the human being is an end in itself emanates from the moral claim that each person has dignity. This moral worth means that every human person is inviolable. Kant tells us that “rational beings are called persons because their nature shows them to be ends in themselves, that is, something that cannot be used merely as means. (365) For example, one might want to get wealthy. However, the human person, being an end in itself, cannot be used to satisfy the desire of someone who wants to acquire excessive wealth.

A moral act, Kant tells us, is that which treats men and women as ends. This means that every human being must be respected as the ultimate bearer of moral worth. To use a person as means is to violate the moral worth of the same. To reduce a human being to the level of things is enslavement. Human beings are free. To violate our freedom is to violate our humanity. The moral task at hand, in this regard, is to respect the autonomy of every human being.

Utilitarianism

Utilitarian morality is a theory that grounds the rightness or wrongness of an act on its effects rather than on the act per se. It asserts that the moral value of an act is one that we can find in its consequences. Consequences are to be evaluated based on the tendency to bring [pleasure] or utility. The motive or reason behind the act is insufficient to determine the goodness or badness of an act. Jeremy Bentham defines the meaning of utility:

By utility is meant that property in any object, whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good or happiness…or to prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness to the party whose interest is considered. (Bentham 1976: 34)

Moral judgment pertaining to an act will have to be rendered after an act shall have produced good or bad consequences, whether or not it results to pleasure. John Stuart Mill believes that, “the creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, utility, or the greatest happiness principle, holds that actions are morally right in proportion as they tend to produce happiness and wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.” (Mill 2007: 6)

Based on the principle of utility, human action by its own nature does not possess any moral qualification. If an action makes one happy, then it is good. Mill says that happiness is the intended pleasure and the absence of pain and by unhappiness, pain and the privation of pleasure. (6) Acts should be considered in terms of their benefit or advantage. An act is morally bad if it results to a loss or disadvantage.

Thus, pleasure, as the consequence of an act, determines whether or not an act is worth doing. If the result or effect of an act is desirable, then the act possesses moral worth. An act that produces any disadvantage or suffering is undesirable and as such, not worth doing. What is only worth doing is that which results to the greatest pleasure of the greatest number. All individuals in society, of course, aim at achieving pleasure. Thus, we must be conscious that others also deserve their happiness.     

The importance of the principle of utility is that it appeals a lot to one’s common sense. Take for instance the desire of donating money to schools. If one donates money to any school, then one is helping children become better citizens. Hence, there is an obvious perception of efficiency and the prudent use of resource. It is beneficial. In contrast, if one gives money to beggars, it has no real effect on the well-being of the beggar. Worst, it can even tolerate his condition and perpetuate the beggar’s poverty.

The Hedonistic Calculus

Utilitarianism judges the rightness or wrongness of an act through a “hedonistic calculus”, or the “measurement of pleasure or happiness.” To be able to strengthen the point that pleasure is the basic moral good, pleasure should be measurable. There has to be a standard of measure, some sort of a norm to be able to put forward the claim that pleasure is the greatest good. If pleasure is non-measurable, then it cannot be the standard, since what people think and feel about pleasure are different.

The seven elements in measuring utility according to Bentham include intensity (degree of pleasure), duration (length of time one experiences the pleasure), probability (the most certain effect is what is desired), proximity (frequency of the pleasure), fecundity (capacity to result to more pleasures), extent (more people can experience the pleasure) and purity (the absence of painful counter-effects). (Bentham 1976: 64-67)

For utilitarian morality, the maximum is always the most desirable. It is the most desirable because it is what provides the greatest in terms of the utility of an act. Mill improves on Bentham’s elements, suggesting that they are crudely based on the quantitative measure of pleasure. He proposes the importance of knowing the quality of one’s happiness. Thus, Mill sees the above standard as limited. Humans experience pleasure in higher realms, for instance in the arts. Bentham’s old standard seems to consider human nature only in a very limited way. It is a kind of hedonism that seems to be crudely mechanical. He explains that happiness or pleasure should not only be about the amount of pleasure. It matters what kind of pleasure one gains. Mill says,

If I am asked, what I mean by difference of quality in pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, merely as a pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is but one possible answer. Of two pleasures, if there be one to which all or almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective of any feeling of moral obligation to prefer it, that is the more desirable pleasure. (Mill 2007:7)

The above suggests that people have many preferences because human beings have a higher nature. Humans aim at achieving higher contentment. This contentment is the highest human good. Will Kymlicka states that for utilitarianism “the experience of pleasure is the chief human good. It is the one good which is an end-in-itself, to which all other goods are just means.” (Kymlicka 2007: 13)

The point is that the ultimate basis of all morality is pleasure. The individual chooses and acts in view of such end, regardless of his circumstance. It is an upbringing that intends to give weight to a life that one finds enjoyment in. The best life, in this sense, is the kind of life where pleasure is found. Mill explains:

According to the greatest happiness principle, the ultimate end, with reference to and for the sake of which all other things are desirable, is an existence exempt as far as possible from pain, and as rich as possible as enjoyments, both in point of quantity and quality. (Mill 2007:10)

Act and Rule Utilitarianism

It is impossible to account for all the consequences of an act. On one hand, the notion of act utilitarianism necessitates that all the consequences of human action should result to general happiness. All actions, hence, should possess the attribute of greatest benefit for the greatest number. Utilitarian morality proceeds from the claim that the [good act] is one that generates the maximum amount of pleasure and the least in terms of pain.

But of course, this is not the case all the time as some human acts have repercussions beyond the immediate effects. For instance, some parent who chooses to work abroad will help provide for the financial need of a family. However, the big disadvantage in terms of the absence of a parent to guide children as they grow up or in difficult situations such as when a child gets sick is barely accounted for.

The notion of rule utilitarianism, in contrast to act utilitarianism, would consider the idea that moral action is that which belongs to the kind of acts, by way of common experience, that results to maximum utility. This means that we are no longer required to consider all the merits and demerits of an act. Rather, in doing something, human action must be one that belongs to a set of norms or a basic standard that has been proven to be beneficial.

The difference is that while act utilitarianism requires that people must act in order to realize pleasure, rule utilitarianism simply sets a standard for morality to achieve the same result. Act utilitarianism relies on our common sense. Sense observation can calculate the utility of our actions. In contrast, rule utilitarianism will provide the guidelines for good human behavior. The rules determine as to whether or not an act results to a desired consequence.